Domenico Dolce and Stefano Gabbana made me sit up and take notice of their Spring 2013 menswear collection when they employed amateur models of various ages, shapes and sizes to parade their interpretation of old school Sicilian clothes. I was very impressed by that collection, so naturally I was curious to see what Dolce and Gabbana would roll out for Fall 2013. Looks like they realised what an inspired decision it was to cast a heterogeneous mix of village boys and men for their spring show, so they repeated it for fall. A wise choice, since it lends the collection the same charm and empathy that won me over several months ago.
There’s less colour in this mostly black, grey and white collection. I don’t care for the religious iconography and floral motifs, but the sombre suits with cropped vests, lapelless jackets and high-waisted, generously cut pants have a classic (some would say clichéd) Southern European elegance that appeals to me. Between this and Anglo-American classicism, I’ve got my style cues all sorted out for the rest of my life.
30.1.13
30 January 2013
24 January 2013
Another good critique of ‘scientism’
In a happy coincidence, I came across this incisive article in
The New Atlantis just after posting about science, philosophy and morality. The writer, biologist Austin L. Hughes, is another critic of science’s
overreaching in matters that are outside of its purview, a trend known as
scientism. A lot of the arguments that Hughes makes are familiar to critics of
scientism: the philosophical ignorance and naivety of its boosters, the complacent
assumption that science is uniquely resistant to human foibles and error, the
failure to recognise the limitations of science in areas like ethics, and the
inappropriate application of scientific ideas to matters that aren’t easily
reducible to facts and experiments.
The section on science and morality (‘The Eclipse of Ethics’)
is pertinent to the debates going on between Sam Harris, Michael Shermer,
Massimo Pigliucci and others. Unsurprisingly, Hughes dedicates a fair amount of
space to critiquing Harris’s arguments in The Moral Landscape,
a book that has become a punching bag for the anti-scientism crowd. In the
following passage, Hughes captures the general sentiment of those who oppose
the idea that science should be the final arbiter of truth and morality:
Advocates of scientism today claim the sole mantle of rationality, frequently equating science with reason itself. Yet it seems the very antithesis of reason to insist that science can do what it cannot, or even that it has done what it demonstrably has not. As a scientist, I would never deny that scientific discoveries can have important implications for metaphysics, epistemology, and ethics, and that everyone interested in these topics needs to be scientifically literate. But the claim that science and science alone can answer longstanding questions in these fields gives rise to countless problems.
And since philosophy
can help clarify the nature of these problems, scientists shouldn’t be so quick
to dismiss its relevance.
HT:
Philosophy Monkey
25.1.13
Science, philosophy and morality
One of the things that I enjoy about discussions and debates
on ideas is when my views are changed by good arguments. Cogent arguments have
almost the same visceral effect on me as seeing well-landed hits in a
kickboxing match; I am impressed by the skillfully executed maneuver that demolishes,
or at least weakens, an opponent. Of course, I prefer being a spectator of intellectual
bouts rather than physical ones. The former are usually more enlightening,
especially when they cause me to reexamine my position on some subject matter,
perhaps even abandon it.
I’ve had my mind changed on the subject of whether science
can, and should, determine moral values. When I read Sam Harris’s book The Moral Landscape, I was convinced by his well-articulated thesis that
science can determine our ethical values. I agreed with his
argument that empirical facts about what contributes to human well-being (and
what doesn’t) can be used to inform, even improve, our existing moral codes.
And yes, I confess that I was inspired by Harris’s bold claim that a future
where moral relativism was a relic of a more ignorant time can be achieved by ever-expanding
scientific knowledge of human nature.
Then I read what his critics had to say.
Massimo Pigliucci had one of the more trenchant responses
to The Moral Landscape. There were other equally sharp critics,
but I’ll stick to just Pigliucci for now because recently he had to school
another Harris-like ideologue who believes that “most scientists have conceded
the high ground of determining human values, morals, and ethics to
philosophers, agreeing that science can only describe the way things are but
never tell us how they ought to be,” which apparently is a “mistake”. Sam Harris’s fellow traveler
is the skeptic and writer Michael Shermer, who is actually one of my intellectual
heroes for his role in promoting science, rational thought and skepticism.
Alas, Shermer’s enthusiasm for science has caused him to set greater store in it than it warrants, at least as far as morality is concerned.
Pigliucci’s dissection of Shermer’s arguments is worth
reading in full, but here are the main points that I have taken from it:
First, Shermer attacks a straw man when he claims that
scientists and philosophers do not believe that science can determine moral values.
No reasonable scientist or philosopher would deny that morality can be informed
by scientific discoveries in psychology, neuroscience and sociology (for
example). But to the extent that such knowledge can ‘determine’ moral values,
there is still a need for philosophical reasoning. Science
can tell us what factors increase or decrease human well-being, but we
still need philosophy to interrogate the assumptions we have about concepts
like ‘well-being’ or ‘happiness’. Science is ill-equipped for this crucial task.
Second, Shermer’s assertions are often presumptuous. For instance,
his claim that “moral values must be based on the way things
are in order to establish the best conditions for human flourishing”, or using the
term “human flourishing” itself, presumes a clean-cut definition or solution
that doesn’t exist. He takes his particular conception of “the way things are” and “human flourishing” as given premises, when it’s really a bit more complicated than that, and not as uncontroversial as he seems to think. People like Shermer and Sam Harris fail to show
philosophical rigour (because one shouldn’t make axiomatic claims on a
priori grounds that haven’t been justified) in their haste to make
their points. That’s just poor form in argumentation.
Third, no reasonable person, certainly not philosophers,
will argue that philosophy is better than science at discovering facts about
the world and human nature. As Pigliucci puts it, “That would be like arguing
that chemistry is better than history at figuring out things about the Roman
empire.” But no amount of fact-finding and data-accumulating by science will
obviate the need for a value judgment on certain matters. And
here is where moral philosophy is required for us to reason
about what the right, or ethical, choice should be. But this isn’t to say that
scientific knowledge shouldn’t influence our moral reasoning. It certainly
should. It just can’t supplant moral reasoning/philosophising.
The ‘science, philosophy and morality’ issue has been an
illuminating one to follow. I definitely think that Massimo Pigliucci has wiped
the floor with Michael Shermer in this bout, thereby demonstrating the
important role of philosophy in making sure that advocates for a (mostly)
science-based morality tighten up their arguments. And start showing
philosophy a little bit more respect.
25.1.13
21 January 2013
Kenan Malik on gay marriage and Catholic ‘persecution’
British writer and broadcaster Kenan Malik has written a blog post about the recent decision by the European Court of Human Rights to dismiss three cases of supposed discrimination against Christians, and the larger issue of religious freedom versus equality laws. Malik’s post addresses the argument by Catholics that the legalisation of gay marriage is effectively an act of persecution against them, since it would “severely [restrict] the ability of Catholics to teach the truth about marriage in their schools, charitable institutions or places of worship”. It’s the same tired refrain from religionists: taking away their right to discriminate on unreasonable grounds is an act of persecution, and contrary to the spirit of religious freedom. These claims, as Malik writes, “not only fundamentally misunderstand religious freedom, but, in their wild hysteria, serve also to undermine those very freedoms.”
Malik’s post is eminently quotable; here’s his response to the argument that gay marriage is a uniquely oppressive example of Catholic ‘persecution’:
And here Malik shows why legalising gay marriage actually extends, not restricts, freedom of religion (emphasis Malik’s):
As for the scaremongering by Catholics where they claim that equality laws would force them to perform same-sex marriages against their beliefs, Malik rebuts:
What about the claim that legalising same-sex marriage would prevent Catholics from teaching “the truth about marriage in their schools, charitable institutions or places of worship”? Malik writes:
Finally, Malik expresses the gist of secularist arguments against religious privilege (not religious freedom).
21.1.13
Malik’s post is eminently quotable; here’s his response to the argument that gay marriage is a uniquely oppressive example of Catholic ‘persecution’:
There are many laws that liberal societies enact that are contrary to the beliefs and practices of many religions. The legalization of abortion, for instance, of homosexuality, and of divorce (and the acceptance that divorcees can remarry) – all legally permit practices condemned by the Catholic Church (and by many other faiths). Are these also expressions of the ‘persecution’ of believers? If not, why should the legalization of gay marriage be so different?
And here Malik shows why legalising gay marriage actually extends, not restricts, freedom of religion (emphasis Malik’s):
The claim that legalizing gay marriage undermines freedom of religion has it back to front. Legalizing gay marriage in reality extends freedom of religion. While most faiths oppose gay marriage, some support it and would like to consecrate same-sex unions. They are, however, forbidden from doing so by the law. Adherents of such faiths are, in other words, legally prohibited from following their conscience. In permitting such congregations formally to bless same-sex unions, any law legalizing gay marriage would extend freedom of religion.
As for the scaremongering by Catholics where they claim that equality laws would force them to perform same-sex marriages against their beliefs, Malik rebuts:
If legislation for gay marriage does lead to unacceptable infringements upon religious freedom, then we – secular and religious – should contest any such infringements. But the fact that injustice may be done to believers in the future is no reason to prevent justice being done to gays and lesbians today.
What about the claim that legalising same-sex marriage would prevent Catholics from teaching “the truth about marriage in their schools, charitable institutions or places of worship”? Malik writes:
[T]he issue of gay marriage is not fundamentally different from many other cases in which religious ‘truth’ diverges from that which the law permits or proscribes. The fact that abortion, contraception, homosexuality and divorce are all legal in Britain has not prevented Catholic priests or teachers from asserting their ‘truth’ on these issues, or barred them from entering any profession.
Finally, Malik expresses the gist of secularist arguments against religious privilege (not religious freedom).
[Catholics] have every right to believe [that marriage is between a man and a woman], to publicly express that belief and to act upon it by refusing to countenance same-sex unions within their church. What they do not have the right to do is to insist that if anyone else thinks differently, and wishes to act upon their belief, they are in so doing persecuting Catholics and attacking religious freedom, and that therefore such beliefs must not be acted upon. Religious freedom is important; too important to leave it be traduced in such cavalier fashion by particular interest groups.
21.1.13
16 January 2013
Christians denied the right to trample on the rights of others
Following the last post on the Gillard government’s craven
decision to let religious groups continue discriminating against ‘sinners’, at
least the European Court of Human Rights recognises that a person’s religious
beliefs do not grant her license to infringe the rights of others. The Court
has thrown out three of four cases brought before it by Christians who claimed
they had been discriminated against under UK law. From the International
Humanist and Ethical Union (IHEU) report:
The Court found that the “balance” of rights had been made for the most part correctly in the UK, in effect confirming that UK law does not conflict with the European Convention on Human Rights with regard to manifestation of religion at work. However, the cases may have implications for many other countries under the European Convention on Human Rights and set precedent for possible future cases of alleged religious discrimination across Europe.
IHEU president Sonja Eggerickx had this to say about the
Court’s ruling, with my emphasis in bold:
We are heartened that the court recognised not only the crucial importance of freedom of belief in Europe, but also recognised the value of the harm principle, namely that we cannot claim in the name of our own beliefs a freedom to impinge on the legal rights of others. The court recognised that domestic legislation must find a balance between competing rights, and that religion cannot automatically be allowed to trump equality laws or the principled policies of organisations. There is a trend among some religious lobby groups to dress up the principled removal of religious privilege as a form of persecution, and this trend is not unique to the UK.
The British Humanist Association’s Andrew Copson commented:
All reasonable people will agree that there is scope in a secular democracy for reasonable accommodation of religious beliefs when that accommodation does not affect the rights and freedoms of others. But if believers try to invoke their beliefs as a defence for treating other people badly – denying them a service because they are gay or claiming a right to preach at them in a professional context – the law is right to prevent them. It’s not persecution of Christians; it’s the maintenance of a civilised society for all.
As Sonja Eggerickx noted, religious lobbyists deliberately
confuse the removal of religious privilege with persecution. They think being
denied special treatment is the same thing as being denied the right to practice
their faith. But of course, this confusion is understandable when you subscribe
to the idea that an all-powerful, supernatural being compels us all to live
according to his arbitrary, and often immoral, commandments. When you believe this, then being told
that you can’t discriminate against gays is tantamount to
being told to disobey your sky-daddy.
17.1.13
Religious privilege? What religious privilege?
It’s no secret that critics of religion are often made out
to be mean curmudgeons with inflated grievances. They exaggerate the harms of
religion while downplaying or ignoring the good that faith and the faithful
contribute to society. Whether they are atheists, humanists or secularists,
strident critics of religion all have a vendetta against any
public expression of religious ideals, and are not above bully tactics to get
their way.
This caricature omits one important detail: religion enjoys
an unjustified and anachronistic kind of privilege that is
denied – for good reasons – to secular ideologies and institutions. This religious
privilege manifests as the automatic assumption of moral rectitude, and as special
treatment from the government, like churches being exempted from both taxes and
certain secular laws. It is this very privilege that allows religious groups in
countries like Australia to discriminate against homosexuals, unmarried couples
or anyone perceived to be egregious ‘sinners’. Given this, it is dishonest of
its sympathisers to paint religion as the disadvantaged victim in any confrontation
with its critics.
Our PM Julia Gillard may be an atheist, but her government
is clearly committed to upholding the privilege of religious groups to break
anti-discrimination laws simply because they believe that a sky-fairy would be
quite cross if they had gays on the payroll. Labor’s new Human Rights and
Anti-Discrimination Bill aims to consolidate existing anti-discrimination acts
into one comprehensive law, but god-believers needn’t worry, the bill won’t
remove their right to deny the rights of their fellow citizens. As David
Marr wrote in The Age, the bill is a “bigots’ charter.”
Of course, religionists like Jim Wallace of the Australian
Christian Lobby beg to differ. Wallace doesn’t think he’s a bigot because
discriminating against, say, homosexuals is simply “a case of looking for
people in employment of staff who represent your same philosophy of the
organisation that’s employing them.” He goes on to compare religious prejudice with
how an environmental group wouldn’t hire someone who was pro-logging, a false
equivalence since the latter discriminates on purely ideological grounds while
the former discriminates on things like sexuality, which is hardly a matter of choice.
Attorney-General Nicola Roxon seems a tad peeved with
criticisms of the new bill. After all, the government’s aim was just to “simplify
and consolidate the law, not completely re-invent the anti-discrimination
system.” Because reinventing the system would mean ensuring that the rules
apply equally to everyone, thereby removing any special treatment for religious
groups. Roxon goes on to remind, and chide, us:
Labor is proud to have developed the sex, race and disability discrimination acts and established the Human Rights Commission. And we are proud now to be developing these important new protections from discrimination on the basis of sexuality… The fact that these new protections are being glossed over by some commentators is regretful.
Nice work Labor, except that religious organisations can
still ignore these protections. And they are allowed to do so because
of the divine mandate they supposedly possess, a mandate that they have
convinced the public and government of Australia (and elsewhere) to be worthy
of privilege. This is the same privilege that gives taxpayers’ money to
Christian Evangelicals for them to proselytise to schoolchildren. It is the
same privilege that equates religiosity with moral authority. And it is the
same privilege that makes criticism of religion, unlike criticism of political, economic or scientific ideas, a specifically vulgar act.
HT: Grant Joslin
16.1.13
14 January 2013
Jerry Coyne has finished reading the ENTIRE Bible
I admire the biology professor and author of Why Evolution Is True Jerry Coyne for many reasons: his scientific knowledge and passionate advocacy for science,
his informed criticism of religion and theology, the unabashed love he has for cats and
good food in often exotic locales, and his commitment to civil discourse on his
website. Now I can add another reason to admire the man – his sheer tenacity in
reading the King James Bible from “In the beginning…” all the way
through to the last verse of Revelation. Talk about taking one for
the team!
Coyne took up this Herculean task in June last year, and
only completed it a few days ago. He joins that elite group of people who can
claim to have read the Bible from cover to cover (a claim that not many
Christians can make, I imagine). Here’s his review of God’s holy word:
I have realized, after finishing the Bible two days ago (congratulate me!), that theology is like modern literary criticism applied to a book by authors no longer alive. Faced with a text that says one thing on its face, but which can be “interpreted” in innumerable different ways, and with no recourse to the “true” meaning beyond what the words say—or to the author’s own take about what she intended (which, of course, can be misleading too!), Sophisticated Theologians™ simply make up their own interpretations. This is such a palpably obvious exercise that I’m amazed intelligent people fall for it. That’s why in some ways I have more respect for Biblical literalists than for clever and sophisticated apologists like John Haught. The former, at least, try hard to stick to what Scripture really says. (Readers don’t need to inform me that even literalists exercise some interpretation.)
Oh, and the Bible is not a great work of literature. There are some good bits—we all know them—but most of it is tedious and boring. In no way is it as good as Shakespeare or Joyce. Yes, it is a cultural touchstone, and yes, I am glad I read it, if for no other reason than I can say I did, and know what a terrible guide to “morality” it really is. But I did not come away with the thought “what a beautifully written book!” There are some good sentences, and a very few good verses, but the book as a whole is leaden. And its vaunted “moral teachings” are, when not repugnant, trite. I’m glad to be done.
In this I disagree with Richard Dawkins. We both agree that everyone should read the Bible for cultural reasons. But to me it’s like learning organic chemistry: painful but necessary. To Richard it is also a chance to be thrilled at the beautiful language. But that beauty is thin on the ground. If you want beautiful language, read Shakespeare or “The Dead”. For morality, try modern secular philosophers like [John] Rawls or [Peter] Singer. At least they don’t advocate genocide or the subjugation of women.
One can almost sympathise with Christians who choose not to
read their Bible in its entirety. Apart from the tediousness and uneven literary
quality, as Coyne has painfully discovered, there’s also the uncomfortable fact
of reading passages where God commands, condones or turns a blind eye towards
decidedly immoral actions.
14.1.13
Subscribe to:
Posts (Atom)